We’ve already seen the Third Circuit Court of Appeals rule that a Pennsylvania man convicted of a non-violent misdemeanor punishable by five years in prison should not be prohibited forevermore from owning a gun, while the Fifth Circuit has opined that those subject to a civil domestic violence restraining order cannot be barred from possessing a firearm, but a federal judge in Mississippi is now going a step further in casting doubt on the federal prohibited persons statute; siding with a man convicted of manslaughter in 1992 who was charged by the Justice Department with being a felon in possession of a firearm.
In his decision, U.S. District Judge Carlton W. Reeves (an Obama nominee who’s served on the federal bench since 2010) said the question posed in U.S. v. Bullock appears to be a simple one: has the government demonstrated that, as to Mr. Bullock, the federal felon‐in‐possession ban is consistent with America’s “historical tradition of firearm regulation”? As Reeves opined, while the DOJ says the answer is a simple “yes,” pointing to 120 other post-Bruen decisions, “the government’s citation to the mere volume of cases is not enough,” adding that in none of those cases did the government attorneys actually produce any real historical record to justify the modern-day prohibition.
To be clear, Reeves isn’t a big fan of the Bruen decision itself. In fact, I wrote about this case last year when Reeves issued an order in the Bullock procedings asking both parties whether he should appoint an historian to help him determine the constitutionality of the felon-in-possession statutes and taking a swipe at SCOTUS at the same time.
“This court is not a trained historian,” Reeves wrote in an order released last week.
“The justices of the Supreme Court, as distinguished as they may be, are not trained historians,” he continued.
“And we are not experts in what white, wealthy and male property owners thought about firearms regulation in 1791,” he said.
The federal felon‐in‐possession ban was enacted in 1938, not 1791 or 1868—the years the Second and Fourteenth Amend‐ ments were ratified. The government’s brief in this case does not identify a “well‐established and representative historical analogue” from either era supporting the categorical disarma‐ ment of tens of millions of Americans who seek to keep fire‐ arms in their home for self‐defense.American history might support state‐level felon disarma‐ ment laws; that at least would align with principles of feder‐ alism. It might support disarmament of persons adjudicated to be dangerous—as Justice Barrett found when she sat on the Seventh Circuit. And it likely does support disarmament of persons convicted of death‐eligible offenses. The power to take someone’s life necessarily includes the lesser power to disarm them.The government’s arguments for permanently disarming Mr. Bullock, however, rest upon the mirage of dicta, buttressed by a cloud of law review articles that do not support disarming him. In Bruen, the State of New York presented 700 years of history to try and defend its early 1900s‐era gun licensing law. That was not enough. Bruen requires no less skepticism here, where the challenged law is even younger.
Besides the advantage of being armed, which the Americans possess over the people of almost every other nation, the existence of subordinate governments, to which the people are attached, and by which the militia officers are appointed, forms a barrier against the enterprises of ambition, more insurmountable than any which a simple government of any form can admit of. Notwithstanding the military establishments in the several kingdoms of Europe, which are carried as far as the public resources will bear, the governments are afraid to trust the people with arms.
The most common mode of reasoning goes like this: Heller protected only the Second Amendment rights of “law‐abiding, responsible” citizens.Heller said that “nothing in our opinion should be taken to cast doubt on longstanding prohibi‐ tions on the possession of firearms by felons and the mentally ill.” McDonald said the same thing. Bruen didn’t overrule either case. Because the defendant is a felon, under Heller, McDonald, and Bruen, their motion to dismiss fails.
Writing in a Second Amendment case last year, Judge David Counts made another essential point:[Step One] is where Bruen conflicts with Heller. Heller called proscriptions against felons possessing guns “presumptively lawful.” In contrast, because possession is covered by the Second Amendment’s plain text, Bruen makes a felon’s possession of a firearm “presumptively constitutional.” Bruen is the controlling standard, but this conflict—the presumption of constitutionality—is what places the heavy burden on the Government.In any event, Bruen’s first step asks a strictly textual question with only one answer: the Second Amendment’s plain text covers possession of a firearm. Because the Constitution presumptively protects possessing a firearm, § 922(g)(1)’s constitutionality hinges on whether regulations prohibiting felons from possessing a firearm are consistent with the Nation’s historical tradition of firearm regulation.
Many of our Nation’s finest moments came when we rejected the original public meaning of a Constitutional provision. Brown v. Board of Education rejected the original interpretation of “equal protection,” which had led to “separate but equal” schools.The original understanding of the Fourteenth Amendment limited women “to fulfil the noble and benign offices of wife and mother.” It had to go. Earlier Americans might not have understood the notion of “due process” to include marriage equality. But future generations did. “We changed.”Hewing to outdated ideas no longer served “We the People.” Hewing too closely to the past reduced our ability to make America “more perfect.” As a result, “new constitutional principles . . . emerged to meet the challenges of a changing society.” And in this way, “the true miracle was not the birth of the Constitution, but its life, a life nurtured through two turbulent cen‐ turies of our own making, and a life embodying much good fortune that was not.”Let’s be clear about what this means for originalism. The next generation will have its own conceptions of liberty. It will interpret the principles of the Constitution, enduring as they are, differently than this generation has interpreted them. Change is unstoppable. And to the extent Bruen and decisions like it try to stop that change, they will not last long. The only question is how long the People will let them remain.